- [ Polynon ]
- [ Whitepaper ]
Noumenal Ontology
- [ Abstract ]
Contemporary models of perception and cognition remain grounded in empirical materialism or dualist metaphysics, often reducing consciousness to emergent neural states. However, these models struggle to account for phenomena such as self-awareness, perceptual coherence, and the structural limits of observation. While systems theory and quantum analogies offer partial insights, they lack a foundational ontology that explains how experience emerges from non-observable structure. Noumenal Ontology proposes a minimal axiomatic framework in which cognition emerges as a construct between consciousness and its self-reflective function, the observer. Perception is modeled as torsional recursion over a noumenal torus, where cognitive structures arise as phase-based geometries. This approach offers a conceptual bridge between metaphysics, cognitive science, and quantum structures through a unified, non-dual ontology of perception.
- [ Keywords ]
Consciousness, Ontology, Noumena, Perception, Manifold, Geometric Cognition
- [ Cite ]
- [ Roibu, T. (2025) Noumenal Ontology ]
1 Introduction
2 Visualizations and Kantian Aesthetics
2.1 The Necessity of Recursiveness
The only attribute of a point is that it marks position. Take away this attribute and in the unposited point we have a symbol of pure Being, the abstract noumenon, that which underlies every mode of phenomenal manifestation, every form of existence. It is at once All and Nothing, at once Absolute Consciousness and Unconsciousness. (B.W. Betts, 1884)
If something out of nothing can appear, than nothing holds all that can disappear.
2.2 Sources of periodicity
2.3 Axioms
3 The Lissajous Projection
In the polynon, a Lissajous pattern represents a 2D projection of recursive torsion across noumenal phase-space, forming the first observable trace of phenomenal differentiation.
It offers a flat, perceptible projection of a recursive symmetry, condensing an unseen lattice of loops into a single outline. Each Lissajous curve is defined by the phase-space differential between two singular points of consciousness: two n+ anchors. This difference determines the harmonic conditions of the projection. Since any two n+ points yield a distinct curve, the system supports an infinite family of Lissajous structures, each acting as a basis upon which further cognitive configurations can be projected and resolved.
Although the curve is traced by the motion of the ring’s projection, the center and the ring remain ontologically equivalent; both arising in superposition within the noumenal monad, where something is equal to nothing.
When the phase function satisfies f = 0, center and ring fully coincide: no distinction, no motion, pure superposition. The moment time-like parameter t deviates from zero, a transient noumenal dichotomy opens, allowing the Lissajous trace to unfold across the emergent phase plane. Each value of t yields a specific offset between the two poles, mapping a unique harmonic slice of potential cognition.
Of course, the “time” parameter here is only a convenient abstraction; defining a prehensive indexing of noumenal potential.
3.1 Tori Polytopes
3.2 The imaginary in quantum mechanics
To understand how noumenal recursion interfaces with quantum formalism, we must examine the structural role of complex amplitudes, specifically the imaginary unit i in quantum state evolution.
As established, cognitive events in the polynon are modeled as probabilistic projections from recursive geometries. A quantum state |ψ> extended into noumenal phase-space becomes |ψ>n, capturing recursive modulation not represented in conventional Hilbert formulations. This evolution no longer follows linear time, but unfolds across a curved manifold conditioned by noumenal constraints.
In standard quantum mechanics, i is the operator that ensures unitary, norm-preserving evolution via rotation in complex space. In the polynon, this same i is reinterpreted as the phenomenal signature of noumenal torsion. However, i is not the noumenal domain itself. It is a structural trace within the phenomenal register. The noumenal field remains pre-phenomenal (recursive, torsional, and inaccessible) while i enables continuity and interference within the observable frame.
This relationship is clarified by a classical analogy: the shadow of a pendulum traces a sine wave on the floor, but the pendulum itself rotates in a higher dimension. The real component corresponds to the shadow (what we measure) while the imaginary component reflects the unseen rotation that sustains the motion. Likewise, quantum systems rotate through complex phase-space, not linear time.
This is why the Schrödinger equation includes i explicitly:
Without i, the equation would yield exponential growth or decay, behavior incompatible with the stable oscillation of probability amplitudes.
The presence of i ensures unitary evolution, which preserves the total probability norm across time. In this context, i functions as a rotational operator in complex Hilbert space, enabling coherent phase evolution and cyclical transformation in quantum systems.
Within the polynon, this formal rotation points to a deeper ontological function. The imaginary unit i marks a structural necessity. Just as the color red is not the wavelength itself but the result of a perceptual collapse conditioned by the observer, the wavefunction is not the system, it is the observer-relative description of phase-potential across recursive structure. The presence of i thus anticipates a noumenal origin: it encodes the curvature of recursion within the phenomenal register.
This rotational structure is also what enables superposition and interference in quantum systems. The wavefunction Ψ is composed of orthogonal real and imaginary parts, and interference phenomena depend on their precise phase relationships. Without i, these oscillations would not align or misalign; quantum mechanics would reduce to classical probability. The ability of a quantum system to exist in multiple overlapping states (producing interference patterns as in the double-slit experiment) depends entirely on the imaginary dimension of its internal structure.
Yet, when a quantum system is measured, the imaginary structure is not directly observed. What is measured is a real-valued probability, computed as the square of the wavefunction’s complex magnitude:
33 I and Non-I
Thus, following the logic of the holographic principle, the curved dimensional interaction between i and non-i, as a pair of orthogonal waveforms, serves as the encoding surface from which p is projected. The recursive phase-field stores its informational geometry on these surfaces. When alignment between i and non-i achieves phase stability, a perceptual event p is resolved, spanning both internal and external domains.
The operators i and non-i define structurally distinct but complementary regimes: i encodes resolved perception within the phenomenal domain, while non-i governs unresolved noumenal recursion. Their interaction forms a recursive waveform.
The Lissajous curve is the harmonic trace of their phase tension: a projection resulting from their structured alignment. I drives the outward curvature enabling phenomenal collapse; non-i maintains the inward torsion that preserves noumenal coherence.
Together, they define the boundary conditions of the cognitive manifold as phase-locked contours, that further structure all holographic projections of cognition without collapsing the noumenal substrate itself.
4 The Perceptual Continuum
5 The involution perspective
What appears as complex cognition is, in structural terms, a degeneration from recursive coherence into representational form.
6 The Polynonial Torus
The non-self is the negation of the self. The self and the non-self limit each other. The self is conscious of being able to limit the non-self, and is conscious of being limited by the non-self. The limitable self is divisible in its consciousness of itself, unlike the absolute self. The absolute self is absolutely conscious of itself, and nothing limits or opposes its consciousness of itself.
Space represented as an object (as geometry really requires it to be) contains more than the mere form of the intuition; namely, a combination of the manifold given according to the form of sensibility into a representation that can be intuited; so that the form of the intuition gives us merely the manifold, but the formal intuition gives unity of representation. In the aesthetic, I regarded this unity as belonging entirely to sensibility, for the purpose of indicating that it antecedes all conceptions, although it presupposes a synthesis which does not belong to sense, through which alone, however, all our conceptions of space and time are possible. For as by means of this unity alone (the understanding determining the sensibility) space and time are given as intuitions, it follows that the unity of this intuition a priori belongs to space and time, and not to the conception of the understanding. (Kant, 1781/1787)
7 Conclusion
One finds himself in desperation asking if the structure, rather than terminating in some smallest object or in some most basic field, or going on and on, does not lead back in the end to the observer. (John Archibald Wheeler)
Consciousness is not an object of description within a system; it is the recursive engine from which the system differentiates, upon which the description is being constructed. Its structure, its logic, and its coherence are not applied to the world. They generate it holographically. Continuously, recursively. Beginning the same way it ends.
- [ References]
- Arkani-Hamed, N. (2024) Cosmohedra. arXiv preprint. https://arxiv.org/abs/2412.19881
- Betts, B. W. (1887) Geometrical Psychology, or the Science of Representation: An Abstract of the Theories and Diagrams of B. W. Betts, London: George Redway.
- Bos, H. J. M. (2001) Redefining Geometrical Exactness: Descartes’ Transformation of the Early Modern Concept of Construction, Springer, p. 235.
- Crupi, V., & Weisberg, J. (2022). Integrating Philosophy of Understanding With the Cognitive Sciences. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience, 16, Article 764708. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnsys.2022.764708.
- Fichte, J. G. (1794/1795) Foundation of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre and Related Writings, edited and translated by Daniel Breazeale, Oxford University Press, 2018.
- Geniusas, Saulius (2024). “The Unconscious in Husserl’s Phenomenology.” Human Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-024-09726-5
- Gosztolai, A., Vandergheynst, P., et al. (2025) MARBLE: interpretable representations of neural population dynamics using geometric deep learning, Nature Methods, 22(3), pp. 612–620. doi:10.1038/s41592-024-02582-2
- Husserl, Edmund (1964). The Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness. Translated by J. S. Churchill and R. Grayson, Indiana University Press.
- Kant, I. (1781/1787) Critique of Pure Reason, translated by P. Guyer and A. W. Wood (1999), Cambridge University Press, especially the section “On the Basis of the Distinction of All Objects As Such into Phenomena and Noumena” (A235/B294).
- Kant, I. (1781/1787) Critique of Pure Reason, Transcendental Aesthetic (A19–A30 / B33–B48), translated and edited by P. Guyer and A. W. Wood, Cambridge University Press, 1998.
- Lienkaemper, Caitlin (2017). Toric Ideals, Polytopes, and Convex Neural Codes, HMC Senior Theses, Harvey Mudd College. https://scholarship.claremont.edu/hmc_theses/106
- Pantsar, M. (2024). Numerical Cognition and the Epistemology of Arithmetic. Cambridge University Press
- Penrose, R. (1967) Twistor Algebra, Journal of Mathematical Physics, 8(2), pp. 345–366. doi:10.1063/1.1705200
- Roibu, T. (2025) The Polynon: A Geometry of Consciousness
- Thompson, P. W., & Saldanha, L. A. (Year not specified). Epistemological analyses of mathematical ideas: A research methodology. In Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education – North America (pp. 313-319). University of Arizona.
- Weinstein, E. (2021) Geometric Unity
- Wheeler, J. A. (1983) “Law without Law,” in Quantum Theory and Measurement, edited by J. A. Wheeler and W. H. Zurek, Princeton University Press, pp. 182–213.
© 2025, Tib Roibu